NexusFi: Find Your Edge


Home Menu

 





Simba, The Best Trader in the World


Discussion in Psychology and Money Management

Updated
      Top Posters
    1. looks_one Fat Tails with 19 posts (29 thanks)
    2. looks_two George with 17 posts (28 thanks)
    3. looks_3 Big Mike with 7 posts (16 thanks)
    4. looks_4 Richard with 6 posts (2 thanks)
      Best Posters
    1. looks_one jungian with 2.5 thanks per post
    2. looks_two Big Mike with 2.3 thanks per post
    3. looks_3 George with 1.6 thanks per post
    4. looks_4 Fat Tails with 1.5 thanks per post
    1. trending_up 16,220 views
    2. thumb_up 97 thanks given
    3. group 6 followers
    1. forum 63 posts
    2. attach_file 5 attachments




 
Search this Thread

Simba, The Best Trader in the World

  #21 (permalink)
 
Fat Tails's Avatar
 Fat Tails 
Berlin, Europe
Market Wizard
 
Experience: Advanced
Platform: NinjaTrader, MultiCharts
Broker: Interactive Brokers
Trading: Keyboard
Posts: 9,888 since Mar 2010
Thanks Given: 4,242
Thanks Received: 27,103

If there is one good thing about trading, it is that you are NOT participating in the rat race! So I really don't mind what those rats are doing.


Jeff Castille View Post
The rat always turns left.........rats are better traders than humans.


Reply With Quote
Thanked by:

Can you help answer these questions
from other members on NexusFi?
Quantum physics & Trading dynamics
The Elite Circle
Pivot Indicator like the old SwingTemp by Big Mike
NinjaTrader
Trade idea based off three indicators.
Traders Hideout
NT7 Indicator Script Troubleshooting - Camarilla Pivots
NinjaTrader
MC PL editor upgrade
MultiCharts
 
  #22 (permalink)
 
Jeff Castille's Avatar
 Jeff Castille 
Northern California
 
Experience: Intermediate
Platform: Ninja Trader
Broker: Amp Futures/ Zen-Fire
Trading: YM and CL
Posts: 2,109 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 1,783
Thanks Received: 3,305


Richard View Post
The rat thing was already covered on post #8 in this thread, and while it's cute to say that it makes them better traders, my point was to question whether that even makes sense. Trading does not feature 60% winning mechanical setups that makes wealth a matter as simple as "always turning left." Too many traders waste all their time chasing the slightly less-holy probabilistic grail.

Hmmmm.....cute or not cute........it just happens to be TRUE.

Follow me on Twitter Reply With Quote
Thanked by:
  #23 (permalink)
 
jungian's Avatar
 jungian 
Ontario
 
Experience: Intermediate
Platform: NinjaTrader
Broker: Mirus/ZF
Trading: ES, 6E, CL
Posts: 97 since Aug 2009
Thanks Given: 88
Thanks Received: 270



Richard View Post
Trading does not feature 60% winning mechanical setups that makes wealth a matter as simple as "always turning left."

60 %... Hmm. Sounds awfully familiar.

Isnt (or should I use paste tense) WASN'T that EOT-Pro's batting average?


Reply With Quote
  #24 (permalink)
Richard
Dallas TX/USA
 
Posts: 153 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 33
Thanks Received: 284


jungian View Post
60 %... Hmm. Sounds awfully familiar.

Isnt (or should I use paste tense) WASN'T that EOT-Pro's batting average?

60% may sound familiar to you because that's the number from the rat story, which is why I used it.

As for EOTpro, I don't know the answer. Bill was always happy to show the equity curve, but he never showed his other performance statistics that I can recall. I'm having trouble making the connection to the topic at hand though... my personal "batting average" is higher than 70% over most time-frames, but that does not mean there are rules that a rat could learn to duplicate or improve upon that.

The basic point, that people will try to out-think a random process, is a good one to make. But I think it's a mistake to extend the analogy any further. It just doesn't line up with real-life trading. I think it hurts new traders to prolong the myth that there are simple recipes for success, and all you have to do is follow them. Buy low and sell high is as close as it gets. Let's see how a rat does with those instructions.

Reply With Quote
  #25 (permalink)
Richard
Dallas TX/USA
 
Posts: 153 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 33
Thanks Received: 284


Jeff Castille View Post
Hmmmm.....cute or not cute........it just happens to be TRUE.

it just happens to be true that rats are better traders than humans, because when you put them in the same maze every day, they can figure out that you usually put the cheese on the left? And when they happen to be wrong the worst that happens is that they get no cheese?

That's what happens to be true? Or am I misunderstanding you?

I hope I am.

Reply With Quote
  #26 (permalink)
 
Jeff Castille's Avatar
 Jeff Castille 
Northern California
 
Experience: Intermediate
Platform: Ninja Trader
Broker: Amp Futures/ Zen-Fire
Trading: YM and CL
Posts: 2,109 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 1,783
Thanks Received: 3,305


Richard View Post
it just happens to be true that rats are better traders than humans, because when you put them in the same maze every day, they can figure out that you usually put the cheese on the left? And when they happen to be wrong the worst that happens is that they get no cheese?

That's what happens to be true? Or am I misunderstanding you?

I hope I am.


So......you've read these studies and fail to understand their application to trading?

Follow me on Twitter Reply With Quote
Thanked by:
  #27 (permalink)
 
Fat Tails's Avatar
 Fat Tails 
Berlin, Europe
Market Wizard
 
Experience: Advanced
Platform: NinjaTrader, MultiCharts
Broker: Interactive Brokers
Trading: Keyboard
Posts: 9,888 since Mar 2010
Thanks Given: 4,242
Thanks Received: 27,103

I tried to find the source for that rat story and could trace it back to two books by Philip Tetlock and Randy Gallistel. Although the story seems to be true, there is a catch. Rats and humans had been given different feedback, which in turn impacts their learning curve. I attach a detailed comment by Mark Liberman below.

In short, Mark Liberman says that the students got more information than the rats, which explains their bad score. This conclusion is highly relevant to trading.


Rats beat Yalies: Doing better by getting less information?

Louis Menand's [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]review[/COLOR][/SIZE] of Philip Tetlock’s book “ [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]Expert Political Judgment[/COLOR][/SIZE]" makes the point that in "more than a hundred studies that have pitted experts against statistical or actuarial formulas, ... the people either do no better than the formulas or do worse". Menand suggests that the experts' downfall "is exactly the trouble that all human beings have: we fall in love with our hunches, and we really, really hate to be wrong". Tetlock puts it like this (p. 40): "the refusal to accept the inevitability of error -- to acknowledge that some phenomena are irreducibly probabilistic -- can be harmful. Political observers ... look for patterns in random concatenations of events. They would do better by thinking less."
Tetlock illustrates this point with an anecdote about an experiment that "pitted the predictive abilities of a classroom of Yale undergraduates against those of a single Norwegian rat". The experiment involves predicting the availability of food in one arm of a T-shaped maze.The rat wins, by learning quickly that is should always head for the arm in which food is more commonly available -- betting on the maximum-likelihood outcome -- while the undergrads place their bets in more complicated ways, perhaps trying to find patterns in the sequence of trials. They guess correctly on individual trials less often than the rat does, although their overall allocation of guesses matches the relative probability of finding food the two arms very accurately.
This is a good story, and Tetlock's description of the facts is true, as far as it goes. But one crucial thing is omitted, and as a result, Tetlock's interpretation of the facts, repeated with some psychological embroidery by Menand, is entirely wrong. As usual, the true explanation is simpler as well as more interesting than the false one. It illustrates a beautifully simple mathematical model of learning and behavior, which accounts for a wide range of experimental and real-world data besides this classroom demonstration. And there's even a connection, I believe, to the cultural evolution of language.
The same experiments are described in a similar way (though with slightly different numbers) on pp. 351-352 of Randy Gallistel's wonderful book " [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]The Organization of Learning[/COLOR][/SIZE]" (which MIT Press has unconscionably allowed to remain out of print for many years). These experiments are examples of a paradigm called "probability learning" or "expected rate learning", in which the subject (human, rat or other) is asked to choose on each trial among two or more alternatives, where the reward and/or feedback is varied among the alternatives probabilistically.
Tetlock suggests that humans perform worse in this experiment because we have a higher-order, more abstract intelligence than rats do: "Human performance suffers [relative to the rat] because we are, deep down, deterministic thinkers with an aversion to probabilistic strategies... We insist on looking for order in random sequences." Menand, on the other hand, thinks it's just vanity:
The students looked for patterns of left-right placement, and ended up scoring only fifty-two per cent, an F. The rat, having no reputation to begin with, was not embarrassed about being wrong two out of every five tries. But Yale students, who do have reputations, searched for a hidden order in the sequence. They couldn’t deal with forty-per-cent error, so they ended up with almost fifty-per-cent error.
Tetlock may be right that we humans like deterministic explanations, at least as a rational reconstruction of our ideas. And Menand may be right about the anxieties of Yale students. However, both are entirely wrong about this experiment. It's not about the difference between humans and animals, or between Yalies and rats. It's about information. The students were given different information than the rat was, and each subject, human or animal, reacted according to its experience.
As Randy Gallistel, who helped run the experiments, explains:
They [the undergraduates] were greatly surprised to be shown when the demonstration was over that the rat's behavior was more intelligent than their own. We did not lessen their discomfiture by telling them that if the rat chose under the same conditions they did -- under a correction procedure whereby on every trial it ended up knowing which side was the rewarded side -- it too would match the relative frequencies of its initial side choices to the relative frequencies of the payoffs (Graff, Bullock, and Bitterman 1964; Sutherland and Mackintosh 1971, p. 406f).
And if the students had chosen under the same conditions as the rat, they too would have been "maximizers", zeroing in on the more-likely alternative and choosing it essentially all the time.
To see the trick, we have to start by describing the apparatus a little more carefully. On a randomly-selected 75% of the trials, the left-hand side of the T was "armed" with a food pellet; on the other 25% of the trials, the right-hand side was. (These are Gallistel's numbers -- Tetlock specifies 60%/40%.) On trials when the rat took the "armed" side of the maze, it was rewarded with a food pellet. Otherwise, it got nothing. But what about the students? Well, on top of each arm of the maze was a shielded light bulb, visible to the students but not to the rat. When the rat pressed the feeder bar, the light bulb over the armed feeder went on -- whether this was the side the rat chose, or not.
Why does this matter? Why does the extra feedback lead the students to choose a strategy that (in this case) makes worse predictions?
For an authoritative review of this overall area of research, find yourself a used copy of Gallistel's book. But here's a slightly oversimplified account of what's going on in this particular case.
We start with a version of the "linear operator model" of Bush & Mosteller 1951:
This equation tells us how to update the time-step n estimate En (of resource density, or event probability, etc.) as a function of the estimate at time n-1 and the current experience C. The update could hardly be simpler: it's just a linear combination (i.e. a weighted sum) of the previous estimate and the current experience. In this simplest version of the model, there's just one parameter, the memory constant w, which tells us how much to discount previous belief in favor of current experience.
Electrical engineers will recognize this as a "leaky integrator", a first-order recursive filter. Its impulse response is obviously just a decaying exponential. It can easily be implemented in biochemical as well as neural circuitry, so that I would expect to find analogs of this sort of learning even in bacteria.

To apply this model to the rat, we'll maintain two E's -- one estimating the probability that there will be a food pellet in the left-hand maze arm, and the other estimating the same thing for the right-hand arm. (The rat doesn't know that the alternatives are made exclusive by the experimenters.) And we'll assume the golden rule of expected rate learning, expressed by Gallistel as follows:
[W]hen confronted with a choice between alternatives that have different expected rates for the occurrence of some to-be-anticipated outcome, animals, human and otherwise, proportion their choices in accord with the relative expected rates…
On trials where the rat chooses correctly and gets a food pellet, the model's "current experience" C is 1 for the maze arm where the pellet was found, and 0 for the other arm. On trials where the rat chooses wrong and gets no reward, the "current experience" is 0 for both arms.
If we set the model's time-constant w=0.3, and put the food pellet on the left 75% of the time and on the right 25% of the time, and start the rat out with estimates of 0.5 on both sides, and have the rat choose randomly on each trial based on the ratio of its estimates for the "patch profitability" of the two sides, then the model's estimates will look like this:

Note that the estimates for the two sides are not complementary. The estimate for the higher-rate side tends towards the true rate (here 75%). The estimate for the lower-rate side tends towards zero, because the (modeled) rat increasingly tends to choose the higher-rate side. If we plot the probabilities of choosing the two sides, based on the "patch profitability ratio" model, we can see that the model is learning to "maximize", i.e. to choose the higher-probability side.


At the asymptotic point of choosing the left side all the time, the rat will be rewarded 75% of the time. (I suspect that rats actually learn faster than this model does, i.e. they act as if they have a lower value for w.)
To model the undergraduates, we use exactly the same model. However, the information coming in is different. On each trial, one of the two lights goes on, and therefore that side's estimate is updated based on a "current experience" of 1, while the other side's estimate is update based on a "current experience" of 0. Everything else is the same -- but the model's behavior is different:


The estimates for the two sides are complementary, and tend towards 0.75 and 0.25. Therefore the students' probability of choice also tends towards 0.75 for the left-hand side, and 0.25 for the right-hand side. Their overall probability of being correct will tend toward 0.75*0.75 + 0.25*0.25 = 0.625, i.e. 62.5%, which is lower than the rat's 75%.
So as it turns out, the rat and the students were arguably applying the same behavioral rule to the same sort of estimate of the situation, and using the same simple learning algorithm to derive that estimate. The difference was not their interest in deterministic theories, nor their concern for their reputations. The difference was simply that the students got more information than the rat did.
At least, there's a simple model that predicts the difference in those terms; and the predictions of that model are apparently confirmed by the results of many thousands of other published experiments in probability learning and expected rate learning.
But why does more information make for worse performance? We're used to seeing evolution develop optimal solutions to such basic problems as choosing where to look for food. So what's gone wrong here? If animals have accurate estimates of how much food is likely to be where -- however those estimates are learned -- then the rule of "[proportioning] their choices in accord with the relative expected rates" is the students' solution, not the rat's solution. The rule says to allocate your foraging time among the alternative locations in proportion to your estimate of the likely pay-off. That's what the students did. But the maximum-likelihood solution is to put all your chips on the option with the highest expected return -- what the rat did.
Did evolution screw up, then? No. In a situation of competition for resources, if everyone goes to the best feeding station, then that turns out not to be such a great choice after all. In that case, if you happen to be the only one who goes to the second-best place, you're in terrific shape. Of course, if lots of others have that idea too, then maybe you'd better check out the third-best. Overall, the best policy -- for you as an individual -- is to follow a strategy that says "allocate your foraging time probabilistically among the available alternatives, in proportion to your estimate of their profitability". At least, this is an [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]evolutionarily stable strategy[/COLOR][/SIZE], "which if adopted by a population cannot be [successfully] invaded by any competing alternative strategy".
We often see a beautiful theory spoiled by an inconvenient eruption of fact. An honest investigator not only acknowledges this when it happens, but searches for such refutations, although no one should rejoice to find one. Here a good story is spoiled by a beautiful theory. That's a trade worth accepting cheerfully at any time.
This post is already too long, so I'll reserve for another day an account of how you can test this theory with a couple of loaves of stale bread and a flock of ducks. And then the really interesting part is how this same idea might help explain the emergence of linguistic norms and other shared cultural patterns. For a preview, if you're interested, you can take a look at a couple of versions of a talk I've given on this subject -- an [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]html version[/COLOR][/SIZE] from 2000, and a [SIZE=2][COLOR=#003366]powerpoint version[/COLOR][/SIZE] from 2005.

Posted by Mark Liberman at December 11, 2005

Reply With Quote
Thanked by:
  #28 (permalink)
Richard
Dallas TX/USA
 
Posts: 153 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 33
Thanks Received: 284


Jeff Castille View Post
So......you've read these studies and fail to understand their application to trading?

As I already said in my previous reply, the only point I see it making is that people have a tendency to try to out-think random processes, which is a bad idea. That's a far cry from saying rats are better traders, though. Trading is so much more than just this one thing. And as a result, people that buy into it are reinforcing an over-simplified picture of what trading is.

I have to say I'm very disappointed in the responses I've gotten here. From you, Jeff, first it was "well it's TRUE" and now "you fail to understand." Enlighten me, then! From jungian, I get some left-field allusion to my former company's track record. I know everyone's happier when patted on the back, but sometimes there are conflicting opinions. Only FatTails seems to want to discuss the actual relevance of the rat story. I thank him for that.

Reply With Quote
Thanked by:
  #29 (permalink)
 
Fat Tails's Avatar
 Fat Tails 
Berlin, Europe
Market Wizard
 
Experience: Advanced
Platform: NinjaTrader, MultiCharts
Broker: Interactive Brokers
Trading: Keyboard
Posts: 9,888 since Mar 2010
Thanks Given: 4,242
Thanks Received: 27,103

There is more in that rat story than meets the eye.

The rat race (search for food under competitive restraints) is similar to a prisoner's dilemma. The strategies adopted by both rats and humans are not the dominant strategies predicted by game theory. The statement above shows that this might not be due to the lack of information, but to an abundance of information, which requires us to use a rule of thumb instead of rational reasoning.

It seems that evolution has hardwired our brains in a way to adopt solutions which bring us closer to the pareto-optimal outcome than any dominant strategies. The rat experiment, however, is not in line with real-life conditions, as it excludes competition.

Maybe, we are simply more apt to cooperate than rats, even if this looks irrational in the first place.

Reply With Quote
  #30 (permalink)
 
Jeff Castille's Avatar
 Jeff Castille 
Northern California
 
Experience: Intermediate
Platform: Ninja Trader
Broker: Amp Futures/ Zen-Fire
Trading: YM and CL
Posts: 2,109 since Jun 2009
Thanks Given: 1,783
Thanks Received: 3,305



Richard View Post
As I already said in my previous reply, the only point I see it making is that people have a tendency to try to out-think random processes, which is a bad idea. That's a far cry from saying rats are better traders, though. Trading is so much more than just this one thing. And as a result, people that buy into it are reinforcing an over-simplified picture of what trading is.

I have to say I'm very disappointed in the responses I've gotten here. From you, Jeff, first it was "well it's TRUE" and now "you fail to understand." Enlighten me, then! From jungian, I get some left-field allusion to my former company's track record. I know everyone's happier when patted on the back, but sometimes there are conflicting opinions. Only FatTails seems to want to discuss the actual relevance of the rat story. I thank him for that.

If the authors of these studies have failed to "enlighten" you.....I doubt that I would be able to.

Follow me on Twitter Reply With Quote
Thanked by:




Last Updated on July 13, 2010


© 2024 NexusFi™, s.a., All Rights Reserved.
Av Ricardo J. Alfaro, Century Tower, Panama City, Panama, Ph: +507 833-9432 (Panama and Intl), +1 888-312-3001 (USA and Canada)
All information is for educational use only and is not investment advice. There is a substantial risk of loss in trading commodity futures, stocks, options and foreign exchange products. Past performance is not indicative of future results.
About Us - Contact Us - Site Rules, Acceptable Use, and Terms and Conditions - Privacy Policy - Downloads - Top
no new posts